Chapter Summary
Definition of
political jurisdiction—What is understood by political jurisdiction in France,
in England, and in the United States—In America the political judge can only
pass sentence on public officers—He more frequently passes a sentence of
removal from office than a penalty—Political jurisdiction as it exists in the
United States is, notwithstanding its mildness, and perhaps in consequence of
that mildness, a most powerful instrument in the hands of the majority.
Political
Jurisdiction In The United States
I understand,
by political jurisdiction, that temporary right of pronouncing a legal decision
with which a political body may be invested.
In absolute
governments no utility can accrue from the introduction of extraordinary forms
of procedure; the prince in whose name an offender is prosecuted is as much the
sovereign of the courts of justice as of everything else, and the idea which is
entertained of his power is of itself a sufficient security. The only thing he
has to fear is, that the external formalities of justice should be neglected,
and that his authority should be dishonored from a wish to render it more
absolute. But in most free countries, in which the majority can never exercise
the same influence upon the tribunals as an absolute monarch, the judicial
power has occasionally been vested for a time in the representatives of the
nation. It has been thought better to introduce a temporary confusion between
the functions of the different authorities than to violate the necessary
principle of the unity of government.
England,
France, and the United States have established this political jurisdiction by
law; and it is curious to examine the different adaptations which these three
great nations have made of the principle. In England and in France the House of
Lords and the Chambre des Paris *a constitute the highest criminal court of
their respective nations, and although they do not habitually try all political
offences, they are competent to try them all. Another political body enjoys the
right of impeachment before the House of Lords: the only difference which
exists between the two countries in this respect is, that in England the
Commons may impeach whomsoever they please before the Lords, whilst in France
the Deputies can only employ this mode of prosecution against the ministers of
the Crown.
a [ [As it existed under the constitutional monarchy down to 1848.]]
In both
countries the Upper House may make use of all the existing penal laws of the
nation to punish the delinquents.
In the United
States, as well as in Europe, one branch of the legislature is authorized to
impeach and another to judge: the House of Representatives arraigns the
offender, and the Senate awards his sentence. But the Senate can only try such
persons as are brought before it by the House of Representatives, and those
persons must belong to the class of public functionaries. Thus the jurisdiction
of the Senate is less extensive than that of the Peers of France, whilst the
right of impeachment by the Representatives is more general than that of the
Deputies. But the great difference which exists between Europe and America is,
that in Europe political tribunals are empowered to inflict all the
dispositions of the penal code, while in America, when they have deprived the
offender of his official rank, and have declared him incapable of filling any
political office for the future, their jurisdiction terminates and that of the
ordinary tribunals begins.
Suppose, for
instance, that the President of the United States has committed the crime of
high treason; the House of Representatives impeaches him, and the Senate
degrades him; he must then be tried by a jury, which alone can deprive him of
his liberty or his life. This accurately illustrates the subject we are
treating. The political jurisdiction which is established by the laws of Europe
is intended to try great offenders, whatever may be their birth, their rank, or
their powers in the State; and to this end all the privileges of the courts of
justice are temporarily extended to a great political assembly. The legislator
is then transformed into the magistrate; he is called upon to admit, to distinguish,
and to punish the offence; and as he exercises all the authority of a judge,
the law restricts him to the observance of all the duties of that high office,
and of all the formalities of justice. When a public functionary is impeached
before an English or a French political tribunal, and is found guilty, the
sentence deprives him ipso facto of his functions, and it may pronounce him to
be incapable of resuming them or any others for the future. But in this case
the political interdict is a consequence of the sentence, and not the sentence
itself. In Europe the sentence of a political tribunal is to be regarded as a
judicial verdict rather than as an administrative measure. In the United States
the contrary takes place; and although the decision of the Senate is judicial
in its form, since the Senators are obliged to comply with the practices and
formalities of a court of justice; although it is judicial in respect to the
motives on which it is founded, since the Senate is in general obliged to take
an offence at common law as the basis of its sentence; nevertheless the object
of the proceeding is purely administrative. If it had been the intention of the
American legislator to invest a political body with great judicial authority,
its action would not have been limited to the circle of public functionaries,
since the most dangerous enemies of the State may be in the possession of no
functions at all; and this is especially true in republics, where party
influence is the first of authorities, and where the strength of many a reader
is increased by his exercising no legal power.
If it had been
the intention of the American legislator to give society the means of
repressing State offences by exemplary punishment, according to the practice of
ordinary justice, the resources of the penal code would all have been placed at
the disposal of the political tribunals. But the weapon with which they are
intrusted is an imperfect one, and it can never reach the most dangerous
offenders, since men who aim at the entire subversion of the laws are not
likely to murmur at a political interdict.
The main
object of the political jurisdiction which obtains in the United States is,
therefore, to deprive the ill-disposed citizen of an authority which he has
used amiss, and to prevent him from ever acquiring it again. This is evidently
an administrative measure sanctioned by the formalities of a judicial decision.
In this matter the Americans have created a mixed system; they have surrounded
the act which removes a public functionary with the securities of a political
trial; and they have deprived all political condemnations of their severest
penalties. Every link of the system may easily be traced from this point; we at
once perceive why the American constitutions subject all the civil
functionaries to the jurisdiction of the Senate, whilst the military, whose
crimes are nevertheless more formidable, are exempted from that tribunal. In
the civil service none of the American functionaries can be said to be
removable; the places which some of them occupy are inalienable, and the others
are chosen for a term which cannot be shortened. It is therefore necessary to
try them all in order to deprive them of their authority. But military officers
are dependent on the chief magistrate of the State, who is himself a civil
functionary, and the decision which condemns him is a blow upon them all.
If we now
compare the American and the European systems, we shall meet with differences
no less striking in the different effects which each of them produces or may
produce. In France and in England the jurisdiction of political bodies is
looked upon as an extraordinary resource, which is only to be employed in order
to rescue society from unwonted dangers. It is not to be denied that these
tribunals, as they are constituted in Europe, are apt to violate the
conservative principle of the balance of power in the State, and to threaten
incessantly the lives and liberties of the subject. The same political
jurisdiction in the United States is only indirectly hostile to the balance of
power; it cannot menace the lives of the citizens, and it does not hover, as in
Europe, over the heads of the community, since those only who have submitted to
its authority on accepting office are exposed to the severity of its
investigations. It is at the same time less formidable and less efficacious;
indeed, it has not been considered by the legislators of the United States as a
remedy for the more violent evils of society, but as an ordinary means of
conducting the government. In this respect it probably exercises more real
influence on the social body in America than in Europe. We must not be misled
by the apparent mildness of the American legislation in all that relates to
political jurisdiction. It is to be observed, in the first place, that in the
United States the tribunal which passes sentence is composed of the same
elements, and subject to the same influences, as the body which impeaches the
offender, and that this uniformity gives an almost irresistible impulse to the
vindictive passions of parties. If political judges in the United States cannot
inflict such heavy penalties as those of Europe, there is the less chance of
their acquitting a prisoner; and the conviction, if it is less formidable, is
more certain. The principal object of the political tribunals of Europe is to
punish the offender; the purpose of those in America is to deprive him of his
authority. A political condemnation in the United States may, therefore, be
looked upon as a preventive measure; and there is no reason for restricting the
judges to the exact definitions of criminal law. Nothing can be more alarming
than the excessive latitude with which political offences are described in the
laws of America. Article II., Section 4, of the Constitution of the United
States runs thus:—"The President, Vice-President, and all civil officers
of the United States shall be removed from office on impeachment for, and
conviction of, treason, bribery, or other high crimes and misdemeanors."
Many of the Constitutions of the States are even less explicit. "Public
officers," says the Constitution of Massachusetts, *b "shall be
impeached for misconduct or maladministration;" the Constitution of
Virginia declares that all the civil officers who shall have offended against
the State, by maladministration, corruption, or other high crimes, may be
impeached by the House of Delegates; in some constitutions no offences are
specified, in order to subject the public functionaries to an unlimited
responsibility. *c But I will venture to affirm that it is precisely their
mildness which renders the American laws most formidable in this respect. We
have shown that in Europe the removal of a functionary and his political
interdiction are the consequences of the penalty he is to undergo, and that in
America they constitute the penalty itself. The consequence is that in Europe
political tribunals are invested with rights which they are afraid to use, and
that the fear of punishing too much hinders them from punishing at all. But in
America no one hesitates to inflict a penalty from which humanity does not
recoil. To condemn a political opponent to death, in order to deprive him of
his power, is to commit what all the world would execrate as a horrible
assassination; but to declare that opponent unworthy to exercise that
authority, to deprive him of it, and to leave him uninjured in life and limb,
may be judged to be the fair issue of the struggle. But this sentence, which it
is so easy to pronounce, is not the less fatally severe to the majority of
those upon whom it is inflicted. Great criminals may undoubtedly brave its
intangible rigor, but ordinary offenders will dread it as a condemnation which
destroys their position in the world, casts a blight upon their honor, and
condemns them to a shameful inactivity worse than death. The influence
exercised in the United States upon the progress of society by the jurisdiction
of political bodies may not appear to be formidable, but it is only the more
immense. It does not directly coerce the subject, but it renders the majority
more absolute over those in power; it does not confer an unbounded authority on
the legislator which can be exerted at some momentous crisis, but it
establishes a temperate and regular influence, which is at all times available.
If the power is decreased, it can, on the other hand, be more conveniently
employed and more easily abused. By preventing political tribunals from
inflicting judicial punishments the Americans seem to have eluded the worst
consequences of legislative tyranny, rather than tyranny itself; and I am not
sure that political jurisdiction, as it is constituted in the United States, is
not the most formidable weapon which has ever been placed in the rude grasp of
a popular majority. When the American republics begin to degenerate it will be
easy to verify the truth of this observation, by remarking whether the number
of political impeachments augments.*d
b [ Chap. I. sect. ii. Section 8.]
c [ See the constitutions of Illinois, Maine, Connecticut, and Georgia.]
d [ See Appendix, N.
[The
impeachment of President Andrew Johnson in 1868—which was resorted to by his
political opponents solely as a means of turning him out of office, for it
could not be contended that he had been guilty of high crimes and misdemeanors,
and he was in fact honorably acquitted and reinstated in office—is a striking
confirmation of the truth of this remark.—Translator's Note, 1874.]]
No comments:
Post a Comment